Clarity is needed regarding moral responsibility, for theoretical and practical purposes, such as philosophical coherence and social regulation. In this article, I examine the notion of (individual) moral responsibility. I first dispense with a preliminary concern, that the notion of moral responsibility can be used in at least two distinct ways, which I argue are necessarily related and hence can be jointly addressed in this article. I then elaborate on what I consider to be the three key tenets of the proposed theoretical approach: chance, choice and constraint (which can hence be termed the 3Cs theory of responsibility); specifically, I consider chance as indeterminate (although calculable), whereas choice and constraint are determined by chance and by each other. I then integrate these tenets to form a rudimentary yet useful theory of (individual) moral responsibility, particularly referring to the iterative process of chance, choice and constraint. And then I apply this theory to three sufficiently dissimilar types of situations of ascending complexity: the responsibility of a democratically elected politician regarding his or her public communication, the responsibility of a person with psychosis regarding his or her psychosis-related behavior, and the responsibility of a parent regarding his or her dependent child’s upbringing. Finally, I summarize and attend to special and general implications of my conclusions, such as the importance of considering expected – rather than actual – impact of chance, choice and constraint, during moral deliberation for assignment of (individual) moral responsibility.
Published in | International Journal of Philosophy (Volume 7, Issue 2) |
DOI | 10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11 |
Page(s) | 48-54 |
Creative Commons |
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution and reproduction in any medium or format, provided the original work is properly cited. |
Copyright |
Copyright © The Author(s), 2019. Published by Science Publishing Group |
Chance, Choice, Constraint, Individual, Moral, Responsibility
[1] | Ward G, Burns K (2017) The Vietnam war: an intimate history. Knopf, New York. |
[2] | Cross G (2002) An all-consuming century: why commercialism won in modern America. Columbia University Press, New York. |
[3] | Garfield L (2018) Mark Zuckerberg once made a $100 million investment in a major US city to help fix its schools – now the mayor says the effort ‘parachuted’ in and failed. businessinsider.com, May 12. |
[4] | Talbert M (2016) Moral responsibility: an introduction. Polity, Cambridge. |
[5] | Ceva E, Radoilska L (2018) Dimensions of responsibility. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21:771-773. |
[6] | Gert B (2006) Common morality: deciding what to do. Oxford University Press, Oxford. |
[7] | Bautz B (2016) What is the common morality, really? Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 26: 29-45. |
[8] | Azambuja LEOd, Garrafa V (2015) The common morality theory in the work of Beauchamp and Childress. Revista Bioetica 23:632-641. |
[9] | Cowley C (2014) Moral responsibility. Routledge, London. |
[10] | Niebuhr HR (1963) The responsible self: an essay in Christian moral philosophy. Harper & Row, New York. |
[11] | Gronholz S (2018) Moral reasons as other-regarding reasons. Ethical Perspectives 25:285-319. |
[12] | Eagle A (2011) Deterministic chance. Noûs 45:269-299. |
[13] | Wiener N (1948) Cybernetics: or control and communication in the animal and machine. MIT Press, Cambridge. |
[14] | Crnkovic GD (2012) Information and energy/matter. Information 3:751-755. |
[15] | Fried Y, Agassi J (1976). Paranoia: a study in diagnosis. Reidel, Boston. |
[16] | Rudnick A (2003). Paranoia and reinforced dogmatism: beyond critical rationality. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 33:339-350. |
[17] | Rudnick A (2015). Choice and criminal responsibility of mentally ill offenders: moral reasoning as a likely mediator related to primary secondary and tertiary prevention. Journal of Psychiatry Reform December 15:1-2. |
APA Style
Abraham Rudnick. (2019). Moral Responsibility Reconsidered: Integrating Chance, Choice and Constraint. International Journal of Philosophy, 7(2), 48-54. https://doi.org/10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11
ACS Style
Abraham Rudnick. Moral Responsibility Reconsidered: Integrating Chance, Choice and Constraint. Int. J. Philos. 2019, 7(2), 48-54. doi: 10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11
AMA Style
Abraham Rudnick. Moral Responsibility Reconsidered: Integrating Chance, Choice and Constraint. Int J Philos. 2019;7(2):48-54. doi: 10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11
@article{10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11, author = {Abraham Rudnick}, title = {Moral Responsibility Reconsidered: Integrating Chance, Choice and Constraint}, journal = {International Journal of Philosophy}, volume = {7}, number = {2}, pages = {48-54}, doi = {10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11}, url = {https://doi.org/10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11}, eprint = {https://article.sciencepublishinggroup.com/pdf/10.11648.j.ijp.20190702.11}, abstract = {Clarity is needed regarding moral responsibility, for theoretical and practical purposes, such as philosophical coherence and social regulation. In this article, I examine the notion of (individual) moral responsibility. I first dispense with a preliminary concern, that the notion of moral responsibility can be used in at least two distinct ways, which I argue are necessarily related and hence can be jointly addressed in this article. I then elaborate on what I consider to be the three key tenets of the proposed theoretical approach: chance, choice and constraint (which can hence be termed the 3Cs theory of responsibility); specifically, I consider chance as indeterminate (although calculable), whereas choice and constraint are determined by chance and by each other. I then integrate these tenets to form a rudimentary yet useful theory of (individual) moral responsibility, particularly referring to the iterative process of chance, choice and constraint. And then I apply this theory to three sufficiently dissimilar types of situations of ascending complexity: the responsibility of a democratically elected politician regarding his or her public communication, the responsibility of a person with psychosis regarding his or her psychosis-related behavior, and the responsibility of a parent regarding his or her dependent child’s upbringing. Finally, I summarize and attend to special and general implications of my conclusions, such as the importance of considering expected – rather than actual – impact of chance, choice and constraint, during moral deliberation for assignment of (individual) moral responsibility.}, year = {2019} }
TY - JOUR T1 - Moral Responsibility Reconsidered: Integrating Chance, Choice and Constraint AU - Abraham Rudnick Y1 - 2019/04/09 PY - 2019 N1 - https://doi.org/10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11 DO - 10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11 T2 - International Journal of Philosophy JF - International Journal of Philosophy JO - International Journal of Philosophy SP - 48 EP - 54 PB - Science Publishing Group SN - 2330-7455 UR - https://doi.org/10.11648/j.ijp.20190702.11 AB - Clarity is needed regarding moral responsibility, for theoretical and practical purposes, such as philosophical coherence and social regulation. In this article, I examine the notion of (individual) moral responsibility. I first dispense with a preliminary concern, that the notion of moral responsibility can be used in at least two distinct ways, which I argue are necessarily related and hence can be jointly addressed in this article. I then elaborate on what I consider to be the three key tenets of the proposed theoretical approach: chance, choice and constraint (which can hence be termed the 3Cs theory of responsibility); specifically, I consider chance as indeterminate (although calculable), whereas choice and constraint are determined by chance and by each other. I then integrate these tenets to form a rudimentary yet useful theory of (individual) moral responsibility, particularly referring to the iterative process of chance, choice and constraint. And then I apply this theory to three sufficiently dissimilar types of situations of ascending complexity: the responsibility of a democratically elected politician regarding his or her public communication, the responsibility of a person with psychosis regarding his or her psychosis-related behavior, and the responsibility of a parent regarding his or her dependent child’s upbringing. Finally, I summarize and attend to special and general implications of my conclusions, such as the importance of considering expected – rather than actual – impact of chance, choice and constraint, during moral deliberation for assignment of (individual) moral responsibility. VL - 7 IS - 2 ER -